At a recent conference, a colleague and
friend of mine from the AAPAE – Dr Peter Bowden –questioned the importance of
moral philosophy to applied ethics. As the editor of a new book on professional and applied ethics, Bowden reflected that most of the chapters on professional ethics, all
written by professionals, practitioners and teachers in the field, didn’t talk
much about moral philosophy. To be sure, all the authors of course appealed to
a variety of principles, values and virtues. But most of these norms arose more
or less out of the practice and nature of the profession itself, rather than
the edicts of philosophies. Moreover, most of the chapters considered the ways
in which ethical practices in institutions and professions could be
strengthened – discussing the varying merits of codes of conduct, moral
leadership, whistle-blowing protection and so on. All this was done without any
appeal to moral philosophy, and such topics are, all the more, not subjects with which moral
philosophy tends to concern itself.
As such, Bowden suggested, moral philosophy
appeared somewhat irrelevant to applied ethics.
As a moral philosopher, I of course
leapt to the defence my profession. I pointed out that moral philosophy was needed when the
answers to moral questions were not clear or held by consensus, and when people
demanded to know why they should, in fact, act morally. These problems for the
most part were not the focus of Bowden’s book. When it comes to professional
ethics, there is usually an adequate consensus on what should be done – what is
required are measures to ensure that it does in fact happen. In cases where
there is controversy we do indeed see a substantial input from moral philosophy,
and this was reflected - for example - in the book’s chapter on bioethics.
But Bowden’s argument did make me reflect
in a number of ways on the relevance of moral philosophy and its impact on
making the world a better place. I’ll get to some of my other worries in later
posts, but for today I want to reflect on the possibility that moral philosophy
isn’t much use in making people live better lives, or treat others more
decently, because it focuses, from a practical standpoint, on the wrong
questions.
My speculative hypothesis (and I have no
evidence for it beyond anecdote and (ahem) personal introspection) is this:
People aren’t bad because they don’t feel they have reasons to do the right
thing. Rather, they are bad because they feel they have countervailing reasons
entitling them to do the wrong thing in this case. Moreover, those
countervailing reasons are not on their face narrowly egoistic or selfish.
To explain. Moral philosophy (and religion
too, for that matter) tends to provide reasons for why people should, generally
speaking, be decent to each other. But outside philosophical disputations, I
speculate that ordinary people (non-sociopaths) don’t harbour any real doubts
about this matter. They are well aware in some fuzzy non-theorized way that they
should be decent to each other – whether motivated by sympathy or empathy, a
sense of fairness, reciprocity and equality, tradition and community, or a
vague sense of the taboo, I think ordinary people believe they do, in fact,
have good reasons to be civil. When moral philosophy comes along and gives a
metaphysical account of why people should be moral, they are answering a question
most people rarely ask or lose sleep over.
But to say that people accept that they
have good reasons to be moral is not to say that those reasons are always – or
even often – decisive. Quite the contrary. One can fully believe – as a general
matter – that one should be nice to other people, but at the same time believe in this specific instance that one is
justified in not being so.
In other words, it is not large-scale doubt
about the demands of morality that is operative when ordinary people do the
wrong thing, but is instead the perceived presence of defeating considerations
that morally justify not doing the right thing in the specific case.
What might those defeating considerations
look like? Well, the pithy pocket-card above is the facetious version. Here’s a
(only somewhat) more sober list:
·
Victim 1: ‘I (or the identity group to
which I belong) have been historically wronged. To find fault with me is to blame
the victim and mistake the real culprit.’
·
Victim 2: ‘I’m fighting against the
oppression of the identity group to which I belong. You are probably complicit
in my oppression.’
·
Crusade: ‘I’m on an
artistic/aesthetic/environmental/humanitarian crusade. If I don’t fulfil my
role, civilization as we know it will collapse. (Or, if civilization is a bad
thing, then if I don’t fulfil my role, civilization as we know it won’t
collapse.) The good I do makes up for the toes I step on.’
·
Resistance 1: ‘You’re all part of the
dominant, patriarchal, hegemonic, capitalist, conformist, politically correct,
elitist (etc) paradigm.’
·
Resistance 2: ‘There is a worldwide
conspiracy that I know about but you don’t. On my shoulders falls the
responsibility to act (or the fatalistic reason for inaction) that accompanies my privileged knowledge.’
·
Exigency: ‘There are exigent
circumstances due to a stressful personal emergency. Again.’
·
Reciprocity: ‘Everyone else does it, so
I have in response. I’m just pre-empting your ultimate betrayal.’
·
Casualty: ‘I’m just an honest person
trapped in an immoral system, doing what I need to get by and do my job.’
·
Sneering: ‘Nobody else lives up to my
high moral standards, or subscribes to my particular political ideology, so I
am justified in my treating them in this way.’
(Unfortunately for my argument, it will perhaps only persuade if it is at least a little offensive. That is, unless the reader feels they themselves flirt with the above excuses when they are setting about doing the wrong thing, they will likely not think that these types of excuses are the problem I contend them to be. If it is any consolation, since I fashioned the list, the reader is entitled to presume they are at least somewhat a recognizable part of my own moral psychology.)
The point here is that when we encounter
someone being mean, callous, power-hungry, destructive, self-aggrandizing,
insensitive and dominating it is probably not
the case that they have decided, ‘God is dead; anything is permitted,’ nor
even, ‘Kant is dead; everything is relative’. They have no dispute whatsoever
with the moral law in general, they just have located a convenient reason to set
it to one side in this case.
And in the next case as well, usually.
Note two points, (a) I think all of these excuses
are in some sense workable. That is, I can imagine being in a situation
where one or other of these excuses applied, and it really did constitute a
reason for behaving what (in less extraordinary situations) would be shoddy or
downright wrong.
(b) None of the excuses are strictly
selfish. That is, none of them imply that one’s selfish desires are entitled to
trump moral considerations. To the contrary, the excuses are positively dripping
with moral unction. What makes them selfish is that they are (I posit) believed
in order to excuse selfish and uncivil behaviour; they are the moral patina in
which we clothe our vices, jealousies and asocial tendencies.
Now it is true, to be sure, that moral
philosophies in principle have the resources to deal with these excuses. Indeed,
the very nub of Kant’s moral system and his Categorical Imperative is, roughly
speaking, not to make a special rule in your own case. And (for another
example) Bernard Gert’s Common Morality only allows exceptions to rules to be
made when the practice of the exception for the reason given in the particular
case could be publically accepted – and I take it most of the excuses above
would fail this test in the situations they are invoked.
But…
More often than not, moral philosophies do
not in fact speak to these types of rule-breakers. They envisage the signature problem
as being naked self-interest, and morality as the cure. But in the foregoing
excuses, it is precisely morality that is the problem, precisely morality that
is the weapon wielded against human decency. So too, philosophy is as likely to
fuel as to prohibit these excuses. Moral philosophy has always been a breeding
ground for radical political ideologies and ‘speaking truth to power’. And since Socrates stumbled out of Plato’s
cave, philosophy has distinguished the behaviour of those-who-know-the-inner-truth
from the dupes seduced by appearances. It has more than a little in common with
conspiracy theory.
Ultimately, if what I have said here is
right, the key moral problem facing us a lot of the time is not egoism, but
exceptionalism – a belief in a profound personal specialness that justifies – morally justifies – the waiver of the
rules. And it’s a problem for applied ethics because any person could enthusiastically nod their heads in
agreement throughout any number of moral philosophy and applied ethics courses and
books without ever having to confront the central reasons they behave badly.
None of this, of course, is to impugn moral
philosophy as a practice, pursuit, study, reflection or profession (which would put me
out of a job, after all). But if the reader thinks there is at least something
to what I have speculated here, then it should give us pause in thinking that
the best way to run courses in applied and professional ethics (such as are
increasingly incorporated into science, law, medical and other degrees, for
instance) is to introduce students to moral philosophy. For in doing so we may
not be answering the questions that need confronting.
The danger is not, or not
only, the rational egoist.
It is the self-righteous exceptionalist.
1 comment:
I don't know Hugh .. I think I take exception to all that.
Post a Comment