In the most recent issue of Australian
Ethics (the newsletter of the Australian Association for Professional and Applied Ethics), Peter Bowden challenged the relevance of ethical philosophy to
applied and professional ethics, pointing out that many of the valuable
practices that predominate the pages of the recent AAPAE book Applied Ethics: Strengthening Ethical Practices have little to do with ethical theorizing. Indeed, he goes so far
as to argue that moral philosophy might even be pernicious. Ignoring
well-accepted empirical findings and encouraging endless disputations, learning moral philosophy is
nothing short of an ‘intellectual handicap’ for ethical decision-making in the
21st Century.
Here I take up the mantle of defending (albeit in a qualified form)
moral philosophy’s relevance to applied ethics – in particular with an eye to
the increasing practice of having philosophers involved in the teaching of ethics to
professionals and budding professionals.
What I am not arguing, however, is that moral philosophers should
have the sole role in teaching and
developing applied ethics. Bowden is undoubtedly correct when he lists the many
vital ways professions can themselves develop codes, roles and integrity
systems, and how we can learn empirically about which measures, legislation, and
practices work and which do not. While philosophers have engaged with some of
these issues, many of them are completely ignored – whistle-blowing is perhaps
Bowden’s most important example here.
As such, I accept that if philosophers alone are left to
theorize, develop and teach professional and applied ethics, they can be
expected to do a very limited job. Often, they will be unaware of key modes of strengthening ethical behaviour, and ignorant of the empirical research
on these. They may be unfamiliar with the ethical issues that actually
confront professionals, and of the difficult circumstances within which professionals
negotiate solutions to them. Worse, they may know little enough of the actually
existing social and institutional practices in a given practice that are
working at promoting integrity – and which the philosopher’s top-down policies
might weaken or sideline.
That much admitted, is there anything left that ethicists can offer?
I think there is.
First of all, philosophy can excel at describing clearly the sorts
of features of actions and situations that call for moral concern. Local
practices, spontaneous arrangements and shared identities are crucial in
creating ethical behaviour – but they equally can be threats to it. Institutions
can display group-think mentalities and they can promote their narrow self-interest,
or even just the self-interest of the institution’s leaders. For this reason, moral
philosophy can be important precisely because of the external perspective it
brings – forcing practitioners to face up not only to the views of their peers,
but also to universal principles of proper conduct.
Second, moral philosophy is important because it can clear away some
popular but potentially problematic philosophical viewpoints that some practitioners
and students may already hold. Here I (controversially, no doubt) name three viewpoints I tend to encounter:
1. cultural relativism: the view
that morality is just whatever the local culture says it is,
2.
psychological egoism: the idea
that people only do whatever they think will make them happy, and;
3.
religious necessity: the view
that the only reason people can genuinely be moral is if they believe in God.
Now I’m not saying that all these views are ultimately incorrect – I
acknowledge there is much that may be said in favour of versions of each of
them. But in my experience these views can be held in a very naïve and
unreflective form. In this form, they can create problems for those trying to
teach and develop applied ethics. Teachers, in particular, need to be able to provide
the basic arguments that may be given to a student who challenges the
course material by saying, ‘It’s all relative really, so why should we care
what you say?’ or ‘This is naïve. People only ever do what makes them happy
anyway.’ There are powerful philosophical arguments against these crude views –
but they are views that often arise as soon as people start thinking and
talking about ethics.
Third, learning moral philosophy can help motivate – or at least energize
interest in – moral behaviour. This is not to say that the first-principles
arguments of Aristotle, Kant or Mill are better fillips to moral action than institutional
structures or entrenched cultural practices. I don’t think that is true. But such
theories can play an important supplementary role – consider, for example, the
many people who become committed vegetarians after reading Peter Singer’s books. Ethical argument can change behaviour.
As a more general matter, though, I have found students can be quite
excited when they are first exposed to a moral theory that seems to make sense
of their previously unexamined moral intuitions. They find that a theory such
as utilitarianism explains something about them, and who they are, and this then plays a role in forming and making concrete a moral identity for them.
Thenceforth, they see themselves as utilitarians, and try to act accordingly.
The link between empirical evidence and
philosophical argument arises in vivid form in what is currently referred to as
‘non-ideal theory’ in political philosophy.
Ideal theory, as exemplified by John Rawls, involves working
out what regimes are just – in abstraction from deep questions about real-world
disagreement, compliance, ignorance and competence. As Schmidtz and Brennan
argue in their stimulating and highly recommended A Brief History of Liberty, this is “like designing
cars on the assumption that they’ll never encounter slippery pavement, or will
never be driven by bad drivers.” Non-ideal theory, on the other hand, from the
outset asks the question about what institutions have a solid history of
achieving (say) peace, rising standards of living and mutual respect.
For these four reasons, I submit, moral
philosophy has much to offer the teaching and development of professional and
applied ethics.
Before concluding, though, I must respond
to the important point Bowden makes about philosophical disputations. These
disputations can occur across multiple dimensions. Philosophy might spark
division because it raises the questions of ‘Why be moral?’ and ‘What are the
fundamental principles of morality’? And it is altogether possible that people
who might be able to agree on the proper response to a moral problem might hold
sharp disagreements on these deeper questions. For this reason, philosophy
might distract attention away from solving what we all acknowledge are real,
important ethical problems by implying that we need to get agreement on first principles. To the contrary, however, if we needed agreement on first
principles before we could start creating practices and institutions that treat
people decently, we would all have killed one another long ago.
Another way philosophy focuses attention on disputations occurs
because in teaching and thinking about different ethical theories philosophers
need to differentiate those theories from one another, and an important mode of
accomplishing this task is by considering cases where the theories give rise to
different moral prescriptions. So, for instance, we are invited to speculate on
fantastic cases that allegedly show stark differences between utilitarianism
and deontology. (And I, of course, am no stranger to such arguments.) And in general philosophers spend much more time pondering the ‘hard cases’ about which
there can be much fascinating and revealing disagreement, rather than emphasizing
how much agreement there is on the overwhelming amount of ordinary issues people
confront every day.
These are important points, but I think awareness of them can
generate sensitive responses. These contentious matters rightly receive emphasis
in philosophical theory for the plain reason that philosophers do not need to
debate matters where there is little serious disagreement. But this narrow
emphasis becomes less helpful when we turn to teaching and developing ethical
practices. There the focus should centre on the enormous amount of issues upon
which there is wide consensus, and direct attention to the project of
motivating and empowering individuals and institutions to do the right thing.
Finally, it is worth remembering that argument does not necessarily mean
endless, confrontational disputation. Argument can also mean rational discussion
aimed at persuading another person of the merits of your view, and being open to
the merits of their's. There are other ways of responding to moral differences,
after all, that are not as civilised. In a world where consensus is rare, the
ability to solve problems by giving and listening to another person’s reasons
is a precious one.
Philosophical discussion, in this way, can be an applied moral practice in itself.
Philosophical discussion, in this way, can be an applied moral practice in itself.
1 comment:
A Reply to Hugh Breakey,
I accept all Hugh’s four arguments. With possibly the exception of his fourth. Of course moral philosophy has added to our knowledge and comprehension of ethical behaviour. There will not be a teacher of ethics in any of the disciplines and professions across a university or college who has not read Plato or Aristotle, nor the many books on ethics put out by today’s moral philosophers. He or she will have engaged in a struggle, often desperate, to come to grips with what is to act ethically, what is wrongdoing, how do they stop it, and finally can they , and if so how, teach these concerns in a course. The consultant or newly appointed ethics officer in the workforce will of necessity have examined the same sources, read many of the same books. And just as desperately wonder how to implement these principles in his or her organisation.
It will have been a time of much learning. Teachers of engineering, medicine, pharmacy, business, social work, etc., newly volunteering to teach the ethics course in their disciplines, or ethics officers in the workforce, will have much to learn. It will be a time of great fulfilment. Even enjoyment. They will nevertheless face problems. Taking the four benefits of philosophy that Hugh raises:
APOLOGIES READERS
WHEN I ENTERED THE FULL COMMENT A SIGN CAME UP SAYING I CANNOT HAVE MORE THAN 4096 CHARACTERS .
YOU CAN READ THE FULL COMMENT ON MY BLOG WHISTLEBLOWING ETHICS,BLOGSPOT
Post a Comment