What could a work, written a century and a
half ago on the opposite side of the globe, discussing neither racism,
vilification or human rights, hope to contribute to Australia’s debate about changes
to its Racial Discrimination Act?
Quite a lot, I think.
Friends of free speech perennially invoke
Mill’s most famous work, On Liberty, because its arguments call into
question the wisdom of allowing feelings of offence to curtail vigorous debate,
and because they invite us to reflect upon what happens to opinions and
individuals silenced by the state.
Our shared temptation to silence the wrong and immoral
Mill cautions us about using our feelings
of moral offence and outrage as reasons to stifle other’s thought and action.
“The disposition of mankind, whether as rulers
or as fellow citizens, to impose their own opinions and inclinations as a rule
of conduct on others is so energetically supported by some of the best and by
some of the worst feelings incident to human nature that it is hardly ever kept
under restraint by anything but want of power...”
We are all of us tempted, Mill observed, to
wield the power of the law to ensure others acquiesce to our desires about what
they can do and say. Allowing feelings of offence to trigger legal prohibitions
amounts to doing just this. But a pluralistic society, populated by diverse
individuals, houses many different perspectives, all with different views on
what must be held sacred. Such differences inevitably result in feelings of
offence when others fail to respect what we hold dear. As a result,
offence-giving is a natural part of a genuinely pluralist society. To suppress
offence amounts to suppressing diversity.
In his defence of diversity and
individuality, Mill argued a pluralist society would need to draw a strong
distinction between moral condemnation and legal prohibitions. Responses of moral
condemnation and outrage must be protected—these follow from listener’s own
liberties of thought and speech. I am free to be appalled by what you say—and to
voice my shock. But all sides in a diverse society need to resist calling on
the law to coercively prohibit immoral actions, and immoral speech in
particular, lest they stifle others’ diversity, feed their own intolerance and
their belief that their certainty counts as absolute certainty, and—in the
final analysis—license the use of a weapon they might eventually have turned
back upon themselves.
Silencing an opinion does not make it disappear
Mills’ signature contribution to free
speech debates lies in asking us to seriously consider what happens to the
opinion and the person silenced by the state. Consider a speaker who wants to
express an opinion about some matter of public policy or interest, but is
silenced by the force of the law. Let’s call our speaker here, ‘Chitra’ (the
name might help remind us that the law, in its infinite majesty, does not only
silence (powerful, influential, popular) members of the majority, but all
speakers, including those who may be disadvantaged, marginalized or vulnerable
in their own ways). First and foremost, Mill stressed, we need
to remember that silencing Chitra’s opinion does not make her opinion, or any
of the reasons she had for believing it, disappear. The state merely uses the
force of law to stop Chitra publicly giving voice to what she is already
thinking.
Two possibilities result. First, and most
likely, Chitra holds firm to her opinion. After all, she has not been presented
with any reasons to change her mind.
Chitra has not heard the arguments that could be voiced in response to
it—arguments coming from those who have different and perhaps more informed
perspectives on the matter, and perhaps even arguments coming from those who
Chitra respects. As such, her opinion remains, and it festers. Chitra whispers it only to confidants and perhaps even
bears it with a secret pride as a badge of her free-thinking ways. She cannot
voice her unlawful view publically, but its presence can still leak out in
other ways—such as when she enters the privacy of the ballot box.
Alternatively, Chitra might change her
mind. But she does not change her mind because she has been presented with
reasons bearing directly on the reasonableness of her opinion. To the contrary,
Chitra cannot be confronted with such reasons until she is allowed to voice the
opinion, as strongly and doggedly as she can, and lay down her specific reasons
for holding it. Instead, she changes her mind purely on the basis of the state’s
authoritative say-so. She acquiesces that her thoughts are so repugnant society
cannot abide their being spoken—though she cannot apprehend why this is so, or
where the error in her thinking lies. Mill asks whether we really desire this
result—whether we wanted to stifle Chitra’s integrity of character and the confidence
to follow her own train of thought. For Chitra’s mind has not been persuaded.
It has been pacified, tamed, subdued.
Mill also asks us to think about Chitra’s
opinion itself, and whether society in general wouldn’t be better served having
such opinions aired, rather than suppressed. Even if Chitra cannot be convinced
of her errors, third parties witnessing her spirited defence of the opinion,
and others’ spirited attacks on it, can judge for themselves, satisfied they
have heard both sides of the story. Indeed, even those welded to the view that
Chitra attacks can benefit from being confronted with her arguments. “He who
knows only his own side of the case,” Mill argued, “knows little of that.” Chitra’s
opponents learn more about their own view, and must search out and reflect on
the most important reasons for their holding it, as they publicly refute her
stance. Whether Chitra’s deviant view proves correct, partly correct, mostly false
or even demonstrably false, Mill contends, society gains by hearing it and appreciating
the responses marshalled against it.
Australia in the 21st Century
All that said, you might yet wonder whether
any of this really bears on Australia’s debate on Sections 18C and 18D of its
Racial Discrimination Act? After all, Mill focuses on the presentation of
genuinely held opinions, not acts of direct vilification and intentional harm.
Indeed, we might wonder how Mill himself would respond if we stressed that many
minorities support the existing law. Far from entrenching his feared ‘tyranny
of the majority’, minorities largely welcome the law and its protections. And
we might wonder, too, if Mill would reconsider if we impressed upon him the
genocidal horrors wrought by racism throughout the Twentieth Century, and the
legacy of racist oppression still infecting our societies today.
I suspect Mill would be sympathetic to
these concerns, but remain cautious about the extent to which we should see
them reflected in law. (I suspect the author of The Subjection of Women would also wonder why sexual discrimination
was not equally prohibited.) With Mill’s arguments in mind, several specific councils
to the contemporary debate about Sections 18C and 18D of the Act rear their
heads.
First, despite all the harms of racism
noted above, we still have reason to be careful about opening this door and
incorporating subjective feelings of offence into the laws’ operation. (18C at
present does this by requiring an objective test about subjective feelings: it
asks whether the act is reasonably likely to offend another person or group.) Human
nature tempts every one of us to use the law to make others behave as we
morally want, with unavoidable risks to freedom and diversity. We must bear in
mind that genuine tolerance requires more than respecting difference: it
requires respecting differences we hate—differences we think we should hate.
Second, we must be honest about the free
speech costs of such laws. Let’s grant that in the starkest cases of
vilification (such as all-too-commonly witnessed at football grounds and on
public transport), where the speaker directly addresses his victim, he does not
intend to assert an opinion, and aims only at immediately harming another
person. Stifling such speech carries few free-speech costs in Mill’s terms. But
many other opinions can be aired in political and social discussions that bitingly
offend certain groups, and yet are genuinely believed and voiced as opinions worthy
of consideration. If we opt for suppression, then we must not pretend there are
no free-speech issues at stake.
Third, if we must limit speech, let’s do it
as surgically as possible, and ensure the general citizenry know exactly where
the specific limitations lie. Consider two potential limitations on speech. A
first limitation would prohibit only speech aimed to offend—that is, speech
deliberately addressed to, and plainly aiming to denigrate, the victim. These
are arguably the worst and paradigm cases of vilification, and in these
situations the speaker aims to wound, not to offer an opinion.
A second limitation on speech, less surgically but still
topically, would prohibit an objective type of offence-giving,
rather than a subjective measure of whether a group feels offended. For
example, we could protect people from hate speech by prohibiting any speech
that asserts the mental or moral inferiority of those of another race (or nationality,
ethnicity) or claims such people should be hated or scorned. Such a prohibition
would protect people from racist speech, but not from race-related offence.
Now strictly speaking, Mill’s worries about
silencing opinions apply even to cases where we are absolutely certain about
the wrongness of the opinion we aim to silence. But categorically racist claims
impact so heavily on people still suffering from current and historical racism,
that even a modern-day Millean might accede to their prohibition. After all,
and despite Mill’s falliablism, the overwhelming majority of us really are
absolutely certain that claims of racial superiority are utterly false and
beyond the pale. It’s not that such claims put forward a perverse moral
view—it’s that it’s hard to see how the view counts moral as all. It fails what
is sometimes called the ‘basic moral perspective’, which involves taking a
position of impartiality regarding oneself and others. Can one really be said
to be contributing to public discourse if one rejects the basic moral
perspective that furnishes the starting point and ground of public discourse
itself?
However: we possess no similar time-tried consensus about other claims
regarding race—such as who should or should not belong in a particular
category, for example, or whether we should employ these categories at all
(questions lying at the heart of the Eatock
v. Bolt case that precipitated the change in legislation). One does not
have to be beyond the moral pale to wonder about the purposes of these
categories and their proper extension, especially when state policies employ these
categories to distribute resources and opportunities. No doubt, people will be
outraged when others argue the merits of whether they belong in one category or
another. Such discussions cut to the very quick of people’s identities and
self-understanding. The feelings of offence they experience are entirely
legitimate. But the presence of such offence cannot budge the fact that
different people possess different opinions about such categories and their proper
boundaries and purposes. Silencing debate on these questions ultimately serves
nobody’s purpose. (Consider the debate on gay marriage—should the current community
of married persons wield absolute control over the definition of ‘married’ and who
counts as ‘married’? Surely not. The debate on gay marriage impacts upon people’s
identities and the social understanding of their relationships—but that is no
reason to stifle the debate itself.)
What’s the upshot of all this? Namely, that
legitimate debate needs to be protected even when we can predict that it will
cause race-related offence (even understandable and reasonable offence). We
should resist allowing subjective feelings of race-related offence to prohibit
such debate.
Different sorts of offensive, racist and race-related
speech
What does this mean in practical terms? Several
different sorts of speech acts concern us here.
Case 1.
Direct vilification: Direct vilification occurs where,
a) the speaker effectively asserts that one race, colour, nation etc is by its
very nature worthy of hatred, scorn or paternalistic treatment; b) there is no
evidence the speaker aims to inject an opinion into a political or social
debate, rather than to merely wound another; and c) the speaker actively
ensures the delivery of the message to its intended target (by email, or as an
online comment directed to them, e.g., or by actual physical presence). News reports
regularly draw public attention to direct vilification occurring on public
transport and at football grounds.
Case 2.
Hate speech: Hate speech happens when the speaker effectively
asserts that one race, colour, nation etc is by its very nature worthy of
hatred, scorn or paternalistic treatment. But such hate speech does not amount
to direct vilification because it occurs as part of a genuine debate or
political standpoint (for example at a rally, march or in a publication or
blog). Consider the KKK or neo-Nazis having a public rally.
Case 3.
Offence taken on racial grounds (but not by reason
of racism itself): In this case someone says something that offends reasonable members
of a particular racial group. However, the statement does not assert (nor even
imply) that the group is inherently morally inferior in any way—the statement gives
offence for other reasons.
Case 3.a: Calling into question whether a person counts as a ‘genuine’
Aborigine (or ‘Australian’, or ‘black’) provides an instance of Case 3. This is
the category that snared Andrew Bolt in Eatock v. Bolt. He accused certain pale-skinned people of categorizing themselves
as Aboriginal in order to enhance their employment prospects. Such an
accusation was bound to be offensive to the people targeted—and would doubtless
have remained offensive even if it had not been possible (as it was in the
event) to prove the falsity of Bolt’s specific accusations through examination
of those people’s histories. But Bolt’s claims were not offensive because they
constituted or implied racism or hate speech. His accusation is quite intelligible
even if all racial groups are completely equal in moral status and respect. As
such, Bolt’s accusation does not present as an instance of Case 2, but of Case
3: speech giving rise to reasonable, race-related offence.
Case 3.b: Holocaust denial provides another instance of Case 3. Denying the occurrence
of a well-documented historical event of profound significance to a given
people, ethnicity or race will doubtless provoke offence and outrage by that
group. In my experience at least, Holocaust-denial seem almost always to be
driven by genuinely racist or anti-Semitic beliefs. But the denial itself need
involve no assertion of racial inferiority or hatred, so legislation prohibiting
objective racism and hate speech (i.e. legislation targeting Case 2) will not
prohibit it.
The Millean arguments supplied above
provide little reason, so far as I can see, for resisting prohibitions on
Direct Vilification (Case 1). Direct vilification adds nothing to public
debate, and intrinsically aims to wound its victims.
The Millean arguments do provide
reason for being cautious about prohibiting Hate Speech (Case 2), as people can
genuinely offer these views as inputs into the public discourse, and suppressing
their views will hardly make such opinions disappear. However, the harm caused by such
speech and its denial of the basic moral perspective arguably outweighs these countervailing
considerations.
However, I think someone persuaded by Mill’s
arguments must fundamentally reject any attempts to prohibit race-related
offence as it appears in Case 3.a. Prohibiting such offence amounts to
suppressing reasonable pluralism and the public contestation of standing political
policies. Combatting offensive views here must be done through opposing
speeches, not legal suppression.
I confess I remain unsure about cases like Case
3.b. Arguably, a legislative act could require certain minimal levels of good
faith for any acts causing race-related offence, where ‘good faith’ implies, (a)
that the speaker genuinely holds the views espoused; and (b) that their views accord
with minimal standards for evidence and fact-checking, in accordance with community
standards for accuracy in the context in which they are spoken. (Note that this
was not the way ‘good faith’ was
interpreted by the judge in Eatock v.
Bolt.) The thought here is that complete detachment from evidence and logic
may be countenanced in flippant comments online, for example, but that the community
requires increasingly higher standards of accuracy in professional blogs, public
speeches, opinion-pieces and journalistic reports. Since blithely denying the
Holocaust amounts to complete disregard for well-known and well-documented evidence,
such denial would be prohibited in these latter cases. While I think Mill would
resist even these prohibitions (and I worry about them too), at least it can be
said in their defence that the process of a finding of guilt would centre on
the available and objective evidence for the falsity of the speaker’s view.
Hence the legal process holds at least some hope for convincing the person of their error, rather than merely taming their mind into submission to the
orthodox view.
Draft Amendments to the Racial
Discrimination Act
The Attorney-General’s
Department released draft amendments to the Act on the 25th March
2014. As I read them, in the context of the above discussion, they would
(rightly) prohibit Case 1: Direct vilification. Worryingly, though, the draft section
would only prohibit direct vilification that incites hatred or causes fear. The
section will not explicitly prohibit directly castigating someone as being
morally or mentally inferior on the basis of their race.
More generally, because
the section will not apply to public discussion, it seems to me it will allow not
only both instances of Case 3, but also instances of Case 2: of flagrantly
racist hate speech that is put forward in context of public discussion. The
draft amendments thus take a very strong stance on free speech (stronger,
indeed, than I have set out above).
I think even friends
of free speech should worry that this amendment swings the pendulum too far in
favor of free speech. My reading (and it is just my reading) of the broad
position of the majority of Australians on the matter is that they think Case 1
Direct Vilification and Case 2: Hate speech must be prohibited. Most of them, I
think, also harbor sympathy for prohibiting Case 3a: Holocaust denial.
If the amendment were
legislated as drafted, I think widespread popular sentiment would mount against
it, and whenever the opposition Labour Party next get into power, we can almost
guarantee it would be repealed. Its replacement would probably be the
restatement of the original act, which prohibits 3a, giving race-related
offence. If what I have said above is on the right track, then the friend of
Millean free speech will be concerned above all to protect speech of Case 3a.
The best way to secure this protection in the long term seems to me to be to
draft legislation that protects Case 3a, prohibits Case 1 and Case 2, and
allows a nuanced position on Case 3b. In other words, direct vilification and hate speech must be prohibited, while speech giving subjective race-related offence must be protected, perhaps with a proviso that such speech lives up to certain minimal standards of fact-checking, appropriate to the context in which it is uttered.
2 comments:
I really enjoyed reading this and will have to re-read (slowly... & take notes) to appreciate it more. I just wanted to comment the first thing that came to mind about free speech.
Fact checking. If only :) A Current Affair and the like would be out if business.
Yes, imagine that. :)
Post a Comment